One of my students, Ori Kowarsky, in reviewing how Canadian prisons
in every generation have generated a crisis, raised the question of whether
"this habitual gearing down is analogous to a stock market 'correction,'
a facile surface crisis which allows each generation the privilege of
breathing new life into the institution and its unremoveable flaw by making
its outward accoutrements according to the fashion of the times" (Ori
Kowarsky, "Penitent and Penitentiary: The Problem of Situating Zones of
Outlawry and Punishment" [University of British Columbia, Faculty of Law,
1998] [unpublished] at 8). The Canadian Sentencing Commission, in its
1987 summary of the succession of official inquiries, concluded that these
inquiries were "more of a tribute to the resiliency of the criminal justice
system than a chronicle of change" ( Sentencing
Reform at 40). At the end of his year-long study in my Penal Policy
seminar, Ori Kowarsky concluded that "the story of the penitentiary in
the 20th century may be the story of a system straining against
the law in order to remain true to its nature . . . [T]he ideology of
the penitentiary is like DNA, it is encoded in every brick, in every bar
and every report" (Kowarsky at 58).
The remarkable resiliency the system of imprisonment has demonstrated
despite a continuous stream of criticism runs alongside the equally remarkable
ability of the system to absorb a succession of theories about the causes
of criminality and the purposes of criminal law. When Kingston Penitentiary
opened, the prevailing theory, as described by J. M. Beattie, was that
crime was a social disease characteristic of the poor, the origins of
which lay in indolence and a lack of moral sense.
Since crime was thought to be the product of a criminal
class that lived in destitution and ignorance, that lived without the
restraints of morality and religion, . . . crime could only be prevented
and society protected if the habits and behaviour of the lower orders
of the population were changed . . . Internal discipline and good work
habits would succeed in protecting property from the envy of the low orders
where the horrors of the gallows had failed. (J. M. Beattie, Attitudes
towards Crime and Punishment in Upper Canada, 1830-1850: A Documentary
Study [Toronto: University of Toronto Centre of Criminology, 1977],
at 12-13)
The expectation of those who designed the regime at Kingston Penitentiary
was that with a basic diet of hard work and religious instruction, outlaws
would become law-abiding. As the penitentiary's official historians have
noted, "At least this was the hope at a time when criminal behaviour was
equated with sinfulness. It later would be called a sickness, and still
later a disorder of the social environment, but the penitentiary would
prove equal to all the theories" (Dennis Curtis et al., Kingston
Penitentiary: The First 150 Years, 1835-1985 [Ottawa: Correctional
Services of Canada, 1985] at 4).
The penitentiary has been equally accommodating to shifting emphasis
on the purpose of criminal sanctions, be that retribution, deterrence,
reformation, or incapacitation. This facility of correctional regimes
to accommodate themselves to shifts in basic assumptions about crime and
criminals may be, as Ori Kowarsky suggests, be caused by a deep-seated
imprint that transcends theories. There is, however, another explanation,
offered by criminologist Peter MacNaughton-Smith: that the assumptions
underlying the theories not only change with the times but are inherently
contradictory, although they share the common feature of justifying the
practice of imprisonment and of dividing society into those who are criminals
(and therefore deserving of imprisonment) and those who are not. In this
parody of the assumptions that have driven penal policy, MacNaughton-Smith
writes:
Criminals are wicked (and we are rather good) but
they are not really wicked, they're sick (so I suppose that we are not
really good, we're just healthy) and in any case it doesn't matter which
they are because the things they do are dangerous and inconvenient (and
what everyone else does is always safer and more convenient) and we have
to teach them a lesson, which they won't learn because they're incorrigible,
and we have to integrate them back into the community, and also symbolize
society's rejection of them. The young ones are the worst and we must
spare them the shame of being treated like real criminals. Now some of
these clichés may well be true, or may well not be, but they cannot all
be true at once; we shall not believe anyone who asserts too many of them
together. They are rather like proverbs: you can find whatever you want.
Which ones the powerful members of the society believe are true will surely
make a difference to what that society does; yet human society as a whole,
over nearly all of its geography and history, has done very similar things
in the name of the law and has offered whichever reasons happen to be
in fashion at the time. When the reasons change and the activity remains,
the reasons begin to look like excuses . . . In our own age (perhaps it
is the age of mystification) the reasons are advanced almost proudly in
self-contradictory pairs such as justice and rehabilitation. But as George
Bernard Shaw says,
now if you are to punish a man retributively you
must injure him. If you are to reform him you must improve him. And men
are not improved by injuries. To propose to punish and reform by the same
operation is exactly as if you were to take a man suffering from pneumonia
and attempt to combine punitive and curative treatments. Arguing that
a man with pneumonia is a danger to community, and that he need not catch
it if he takes proper care of his health, you resolve that he shall have
a severe lesson, both to punish him for his negligence and pulmonary weakness
and to deter others from following his example. You therefore strip him
naked, and in that condition stand him all night in the snow. But as you
admit the duty of restoring him to health if possible, and discharging
him with sound lungs, you engage a doctor to superintend the punishment
and administer cough lozenges made as unpleasant to the taste as possible
so as not to pamper the culprit. A board of commissioners ordering such
treatment would prove thereby that either they were imbeciles or else
that they were hotly in earnest about punishing the patient and not in
the least in earnest about curing him. (P. MacNaughton-Smith, Permission
to be Slightly Free [Ottawa: Minister of Supply and Services Canada,
1976] at 30-32)
With so many contradictory assumptions supporting penal policy, is it
so strange that the institution of imprisonment has, chameleon-like, developed
the ability to present itself in many different colours over time, from
Revenge to Restraint, from Restraint to Reformation, and from Reformation
to Reintegration? Page 4 of 9
|